Immanuel
Kant (1724- 1804) was a respected German philosopher that was known for
developing the Kantian ethic structure. His sense of virtues was based on the theory
that is known as the Categorical Imperative. According to Kant, the Categorical
Imperative represents the duty of
human beings, which is to perfect ourselves, and to promote happiness onto
others (Timmons 213). Kant believes that if humans cannot sufficiently follow
the Categorical Imperative, then we do not respect humanity, or ourselves as
ends. He explains that we should not use each other as only a mean, but as an
end. Being an end is being something that you are respected for. But before we
can accept each other as ends, we must first be able to perceive what is just, and
what isn’t just—we must use our rationality to do this. With rationality
undergone, we must learn to use our autonomy or “freedom” as individuals. With
the ability autonomy we have to explore our ideas of what is rational, and what isn’t rational.
In
opposition to the above stated, John Stuart Mill (1806-1873) was a respected
British philosopher who believed in ethical morals of Utilitarianism.
Utilitarianism is the belief that it is in everyone to pursue happiness as an
aim, in life. Mill often rebuts against such claims that says for example, “the
‘Utilitarian’ view that life has no higher end—no better and nobler desire and
pursuit—than pleasure they describe as utterly mean and grovelling, a doctrine
worthy of only pigs” (Mill 5). Mill disputes this topic by expressing that if
Utilitarian’s are considered pigs because of their belief of pleasure as an
end, than every philosophical stature has to have pig-like qualities as well, for
we are all humans, and if what’s considered the
rule of life makes Utilitarian’s happy as pigs, must also make their equals
(the opposing theories) happy as pigs. Secondly, Mill clearly explains that the
moral virtues of Utilitarian’s—desires and pleasures free from pain—are what is
evidently somewhere acclaimed in other “theories of morality.”
Personally,
I side more with Utilitarianism because it is true that Kantian ethics has in
their doctrine the idea of happiness, or the idea of self-gratification,
ultimately. One example is self-perfection. Timmons even says in an analysis of
Kant’s moral ethics called “Kant’s System
of Duties” that human beings do not need to go on promoting happiness
within themselves because that is already an intrinsic human ability (213). Kantian
ethics may sound as if it can be done easily, but learning 1) The duty of
self-perfection 2) The duty to promote the happiness of others, can take quite
some time, especially because we must first promote our own rationality and
autonomy to then be capable of encouraging good traits onto others. What Mill
most nearly means of utilitarianism is that when we are happy within, and for
ourselves, we have the ability to be capacitated with enough knowledge of
passing this confidence onto others. Kant’s moral ethics are demanding, in a
way.
Barbara
Argument
If The Golden Rule constitutes the ideal
perfection of utilitarian morality
Then all agents of good act follow The
Golden Rule
Therefore, all agents of the act are the
ideal perfection of utilitarian morality
Iesha,
ReplyDeleteI like your post and thought you did a good job on it and I liked that you incorporated some quotes. The only thing I was a little confused about was your Barbara argument, it doesn't really make a lot of sense and I think there might be a typo in the last sentence.
Thank you. I see the typo :)
Delete